Home
Home





Nederlands






Texts/
Articles





Workshops





Naud van der Ven





Contact










Click here for blogmessages



Levinas and Gender

Parallels between the dynamics of the gender debate and a radical interpretation of Emmanuel Levinas’s thinking

(Published in Dutch in Mededelingen van de Levinas Studiekring, XXVI, december 2021)





Introduction with thesis

This article is the fruit of two streams of ideas that have crossed my path over the past year and a half. The first stream is that of the gender discussion, which has of course been going on for much longer, but has apparently only recently become unavoidably topical for me. The other stream is that of the book Un-common Sociality. Thinking sociality with Levinas by the Swedish philosopher Ramona Rat, which I was able to take a closer look at due to the relative calm of the corona lockdown.

The first stream follows closely concrete persons and groups of whom I pick up the ideas from an almost daily flood of articles in – mainly Dutch – newspapers and magazines, and sometimes from books. The resulting harvest presented in this article is largely from the summer of 2021. The second stream, derived almost entirely from Rat’s book on the thinking of the French-Jewish philosopher Emmanuel Levinas (1906 – 1995), is more theoretical and moves through an intellectual space of notions and concepts.

Remarkably enough, in my head, the two streams appeared to cross each other and form a connection. This is expressed in the following thesis that I gradually formulated:

Much of what Levinas, according to Ramona Rat, brings about in his thinking on sociality resembles the dynamics generated by the gender movement.

The purpose of this article is to further substantiate this thesis. I will do this by first (Section 1) pointing out in a somewhat superficial way phenomena that occur both in the gender movement  and, according to Rat, in Levinas. This involves the blurring of traditional concepts, the creation of new language and the irritation that the blurring and the new language evoke. Then (Section 2) I will formulate a common denominator for these phenomena, both in the debate about gender and that about Levinas, namely: the presence or absence of ontological security. I explain this concept and on that basis I, in Section 3, reformulate the thesis in terms of ontological security. This makes it possible to identify more deeply and more explicitly the parallels that I could intuitively point out between the two areas, and thus to substantiate the thesis (Sections 4 and 5). This substantiation enables me to articulate what is at stake in both dynamics: liberation from forms of closedness. Then it also becomes clear (Section 6) that the gender movement has already taken significant steps on the path of that liberation. I conclude by expressing the expectation that Rat’s interpretation of Levinas can further support such kinds of liberation.

1. Parallels at first sight regarding use of language in the gender movement and in Levinas

Between the dynamics of the gender movement on the one hand, and what in Rat’s view is happening in Levinas’s work with regard to the theme of sociality on the other hand, the following parallels can be noted: the blurring of traditional concepts, the search for new language, and the irritation about those two phenomena.

Blurring of traditional concepts

In the field of gender discussions, the most striking feature is the blurring of the terms ‘man’ and ‘woman’. The fixed definition of these concepts appears to be under discussion in the current gender debates, the demarcation of the genders in relation to each other seems to be becoming fluid. This is apparent, for example, in the relativization of gender differences by transgender Ian Morris, who thinks the word ‘change’ sounds too heavy for her transition from male to female. “I haven’t changed gender, it’s never been so black and white for me: I’ve absorbed one into the other, I’m a bit of both now.”  The blurring of the line between the two is also apparent from the sensitivity to the obvious link between pregnancy and women, and the call to say ‘pregnant human being’ instead of ‘pregnant woman’ . What once was considered exclusively pertaining to women, pregnancy, turns out to be a possibility that can also be attributed to men.

This is drastic. If – in the mind of most people – there is one thing that has been fixed since the very beginning of mankind, it was the difference between man and woman, attributing specific characteristics to each of the two categories. This dichotomy – binarity – has apparently been so fundamental for centuries that it has left its mark on the patterns of our language. Linguist Marc van Oostendorp points out that in language the grammatical gender is an age-old fact. Language is interspersed with the dichotomy between man and woman, for example in personal pronouns and nouns. If this dichotomy disintegrates at the conceptual level, this will have immediate consequences for everyday language use. Because how do you designate someone who is neither he nor she, that is: non-binary? 

Then over to Levinas. One example of his blurring of concepts is that he doesn’t seem to mind talking, when he speaks about the ethical relationship that can exist between people, about a ‘relationship without relationship’. Because if in one place he describes that relationship with another human being comprehensibly as “the direct and full face welcome of the other by me”  , he says in another place: “For the relation between the being here below and the transcendent being that results is no community of concept or totality – a relation without relation (…)” .

Another example of a possibly shocking lack of clarity, or irritating deliberate vagueness, is when Levinas speaks of a contradiction such as that between an active and a passive human attitude which at first sight is not too complicated. In common parlance, the first attitude is linked to showing initiative, making a start, for example in approaching another person. Not so with Levinas, as commentator Rat points out: she calls Levinas apparently careless “when it comes to attributing the approach to an initiator” , thereby blurring the familiar opposition between activity and passivity.

One more example: in general it is clear that there is a difference between inside and outside. That is, quite simply, determined by the dividing line that lies between those two categories. For a house, that dividing line is the outer wall, which makes it irrefutably clear what you call inside and what you call outside. Common parlance sees this happening in people too: some things take place in your mind, others outside or in other minds. The premise here, as with the outer wall of the house, is that there is a clear boundary between the two minds. Levinas gleefully mixes up things when, according to Rat, he says that “the interiority of the self is not its own, but is given through the other (…) and in this way, it is an opened-up interiority. Here, the relative determination between the inside and outside is disturbed. The inside is not determined by the boundaries of the outside, but the self is from the start invaded by the outside” .

New language

For those who want to say new things, language can apparently have a limiting effect. The words in which the new can be said are not readily available and common strict distinctions in the traditional language can feel oppressive. An obvious way out is to invent new words or to give existing words a different meaning. We see that happening within the gender movement and with Levinas and, following in his footsteps, Ramona Rat.

In the past decade, the gender movement has been actively searching for new words to soften the strong rootedness of binarity in language. Because in most languages this dichotomy is deeply anchored in the personal pronouns (she, he, him, her), much of the effort is focused on launching new, non-binary personal pronouns.

This seems to have worked out quite well in Sweden. Journalist Sander Becker talks about this in his article Is Dutch ready for the gender-neutral ‘Hen runs’? : “At the beginning of this century, the Swedish LGBTQI+ community started promoting the gender-neutral ‘hen’ alongside ‘han’ (he) and ‘hon’ (she). With success: the word received a lot of media attention and caught on. In 2014, ‘hen’ was included in the dictionary of the Swedish academy. The word has two meanings: it can refer to a person whose gender is irrelevant – say the ‘he/she’ from a job ad – or it can refer to a non-binary individual”. The Swedish media use ‘hen’ a lot. Becker points out that the success of ‘hen’ in Sweden is partly due to the fact that the word differs from ‘han’ and ‘hon’ by only one vowel, which makes it less noticeable. That helps acceptance.

English has a similar advantage with the words ‘they/their’, which apart from the common non-binary plural can also be used to indicate the non-binary singular. The latter meaning has historical roots. Since the Middle Ages, you can refer to a general person in English as “they” regardless of gender, which aids the contemporary use of the word as a gender-neutral designation.

For Dutch this kind of new use of pronouns is more difficult to achieve because a fluent connection with history (as in English) or with existing words (as in Swedish) is not available. Becker talks about an attempt by the Dutch Transgender Network to have a gender update of the Dutch language: “In 2016, the foundation conducted a survey among 500 non-binary Dutch people. Participants could choose from three alternatives for the Dutch equivalents of the personal and possessive pronouns he/him/his and she/her/her. The options were: die/die/diens, or hen/hen/hun or dee/dem/dijr” .

Linguist Van Oostendorp is quite skeptical about such attempts at artificially creating gender-neutral pronouns. “They are a system, a conservative force. You don’t do much about that.”  That is: you don’t just change them because they are embedded in the foundation of a language. Nevertheless, the change has officially been partially implemented in the Netherlands. The Dictionary of the Dutch Language Van Dale took the plunge and now ‘hen’ is included in the dictionary as a reference to a non-binary person. The news agency ANP, supplier of almost all Dutch media, adopts gender-neutral pronouns from the Dutch Transgender Network, with ‘hen’ or ‘die’ for non-binary persons.

In addition, in the public discussion about gender diversity, new customs and words continue to emerge, that should help to make visible the newly felt fluidity of gender boundaries. For example, secondary school teachers Borsboom and Draaisma  say that at their school it is not only increasingly common for students to insert desired pronouns above their digital profile or after their e-mail signature, but also that teachers and students are inventing new ways of addressing the teacher, such as ‘mevreer’ or ‘menouw’ which are composed of elements of ‘mevrouw’ (female) and ‘meneer’ (male).

If, as we saw, Levinas sometimes questions usual contradictions or creates unusual combinations, he often finds it difficult to use the words that are available in the handed down arsenal of language. He then has to create new words, or give existing words a new meaning. Where, for example, he tampers with the traditional sharp boundary between subject and object, he resorts as we shall see below to the word ‘substitution’. When he starts treating the concept of passivity in his own way, he likes to use the expression ‘more passive than all passivity’ .

Sometimes it is not Levinas himself, but an interpreter of his work who arrives at new language use on the basis of Levinas’s reasoning. We’ll see that this applies to Ramona Rat. Following Levinas’s intertwining of inside and outside, she proposes to speak of ‘opened-up interiority’ , in which, as we have seen, “the interiority of the self is not its own, but is given through the other” . You could say that the self is turned ‘inside out’, or ‘outside in’.

Irritation

Blurring of familiar concepts can create discomfort, and the confrontation with artificial new words or word meanings can feel forced and irritating. These reactions do indeed occur to both the gender movement and Levinas. When it comes to the dynamics of the gender movement, the irritated reactions can be easily scooped out of the media on almost daily basis. A selection from this:

“There is nothing wrong with ‘pregnant person’, but why should ‘pregnant woman’ give way to that?”

“The concepts of woman and man belong to all of us, just like mother and father. Egg cell and sperm: who didn’t grow up with them?”

“For example, ‘woman’ is suddenly removed from the dictionary.”

“The French language will perish if the existence of gender-neutral pronouns is recognized.”

“Isn’t it better then to eliminate the phenomenon of language?”

Journalist Menno Sedee notes that non-binary people in the Netherlands apparently still cause a lot of discomfort. In 2018, the Social and Cultural Planning Office calculated that 20 percent of adult Dutch people believe that “something is wrong with people who do not feel like a man or a woman”. Almost half think it is “important to know whether someone is a man or a woman” . Apparently ideas, opinions and feelings about what that is, ‘man’ or ‘woman’, have a strong effect. We all have them – and usually we cherish them .

With regard to Levinas’s use of words, I will confine myself for the moment to pointing out my own regularly emerging skepticism and irritation. When I read about ‘a relationship without a relationship’, the ‘unknowability of the face’ or similar paradoxical statements about the ‘thematization of the unthematizable’, is it still about something? Or is this just word play? How vague can you be? Perhaps these questions are the motive for me to write this article.

2. A common denominator for those parallels: ontological (in)security

The blurring of traditional concepts, the creation of new words or word meanings and the associated discomfort can be labeled as ‘ontological insecurity’. Or vice versa: the loss of ‘ontological security’, where ontological security roughly stands for the possession (in individuals or groups) of a firm and stable identity that does not like too much change. But this description is too rough to serve in this article. If we want to be more precise, two schools can be distinguished that interpret the concept of ontological security differently: the existentialist variant and the epistemological variant. By briefly describing both variants below and then choosing the epistemological variant, I try to make clear how I will use the concept of ontological security, and thus also its opposite, ontological insecurity.

The existentialist conception of ontological security

In the last twenty years there has been an explosion of books and articles that present themselves as ‘ontological security literature’. It covers such diverse fields as international relations, psychiatry, and sociology. Due to the variety of subjects, the confusion of tongues in this literature is sometimes great, and thus also the meaning of the word ontological (in)security. But thanks in part to the efforts of Karl Gustaffson and Chris Rossdale, it is possible in the ontological security literature to demarcate the existentialist variant from the epistemological variant of ontological security.

The term ontological security comes from the existentialist direction. It was coined around 1960 by the psychiatrist Ronald Laing in his book The Divided Self, with the intention of formulating an existentialist approach to psychoanalysis. Laing says of ontological security: “The individual (…) may experience his own being as real, alive, whole; as differentiated from the rest of the world in ordinary circumstances so clearly that his identity and autonomy are never in question; as a continuum in time; as having an inner consistency, substantiality, genuineness, and worth; as spatially coextensive with the body; and, usually, as having begun in or around birth and liable to extinction with death. He thus has a firm core of ontological security” .

You could say: for Laing, an ontologically secure person is a one-piece person, possessing an unshakable, stable identity. And in that way of being, Laing emphasizes, a person finds the opportunity to interact authentically with other people and to lead a social life. That Laing in his conception of ontological security is inspired by existentialist philosophy is apparent from his attention to the finiteness of human existence and the fear that confrontation with it can evoke in man. Face to face with this, we must realize, says Laing, that absolute security is unattainable and that we do not have complete control over what happens to us. The solidity of the autonomous subject, or: ontological security, enables us to deal with it. In this regard, Laing refers to the notion of ‘the courage to be’, taken from the book of the same name by the existentialist Paul Tillich, which emphasizes the importance of “facing anxiety as well as the possibility of obtaining a feeling of ontological security in spite of such anxiety” .

The word ‘ontological’ is used here adverbially, in the sense of ‘concerning the way of being’. The etymology of the word ontology allows this, because it is composed of the Greek words ontos (genitive of on which can be translated as ‘existence’ or ‘being’) and logos, that is, ‘doctrine’, ‘interpretation’, or ‘explanation’; so, put together: teachings about (the way of) existence. Ontological security then means: the certainty of the subject about his way of being. Clearly the term originated in the field of psychiatry, where it referred to individuals. But then the term found its way into all sorts of other fields, where it was applied not only to individuals but also to groups of people or states.

The sociologist Anthony Giddens introduced the term to sociology. For Giddens, ontological security stands for the sense of identity and orientation that people in society derive from legal, cultural and existential narratives, conceived as practices of daily life that have become routine, through which you can find your way there. Rossdale explains: “The coherence of these practices, and the narrative around which they form, becomes central to an actor’s capacity to act, to have sufficient confidence in their space and narrative of being to make choices and interventions” . From there, the existentialist concept of ontological security has subsequently spread to and been used extensively in the field of the science of international relations (IR). IR studies took a big step by applying the notions of ontological security or insecurity to states, depending on the degree of confidence they have in themselves and the international legal order. In this way ontological security could take on the meaning of a state’s certainty about its existence and way of acting.

The epistemological conception of ontological security

The other way of using the word combination ontological security addresses the interpretation of the part ‘on’ (in ontology) not as a ‘way of being’ but as ‘that which is’, being. Then ontology is an ‘explanation of that which is’, in other words: clarification of everything that is, whereby the clarification takes place, among other things, by dividing that which is (the beings) into levels and categories. This ontology claims to have insight into the world, and is thus epistemological in nature. In line with this, ontological security then becomes: the feeling that the available explanation of what is, is correct; that the ordering of the world that the ontology provides is convincing. This epistemological variant of ontological security is much older than the existentialist one, it fits in with the meaning that the word ontology has had since time immemorial, at least in the West from the Ancient Greeks. For two and a half thousand years, ontology in the sense of the explanation and arrangement of being and beings has been an essential part of Western philosophy.

This variant of ontological security also uses routines and stories and meaningful constructions. But they are less focused on embedding a practical existence and more on acquiring knowledge. The epistemological commitment of these routines appears from the centrality of logical clarification and ordering and from the cognitive claim that emanates from them. I think Chris Rossdale uses ontological security in this sense in his article Enclosing Critique: The Limits of Ontological Security. Speaking of ontological security, he states that “[i]n placing certain assumptions and routines at the level of common sense, and in being able to trust in the stability of these routines, actors are able to build narratives, stories and plans without being perpetually confronted by the contingent nature of their foundations” . From Rossdale’s emphasis on ‘common sense’ in achieving ontological security, I infer that in his view the order afforded by assumptions and routines must be persuasive to the mind—however superficially—and thereby claims cognitive validity.

The knowledge claim is characteristic of ontological security in the epistemological sense of the word combination. This variant of ontological security pretends to have certainty about what is and about the organization of the world. Ontological security sees the world as a coherent whole that is knowable. In order to achieve this closed arrangement, this epistemological ontology is based on a synthetic unitarian thinking: all elements, categories and levels of the thought order are connected, whether or not by hierarchical lines, to the highest principle of the order (often God, but it can also be nature) and with each other. Furthermore, to fill in the various categories, one falls back on the ‘essence’ of each category of beings. This is obtained by a process of abstracting from the really existing instances of that category. Thus for the category of woman an ‘essence of the female’ arises and for the category of man an ‘essence of the male’, as abstractions of the real existing women and men.

How far this deviates from the existentialist ontological security can be deduced from Laing’s aversion to the epistemological variant. In his defense of the existentialist ontological security, he points to the fundamental character of the existentialist sense of self in relation to traditional philosophy: “It (the sense of self, NvdV) exists prior to the scientific or philosophical difficulties about how such experience is possible or how it is to be explained” . For the existentialists, interpretation of one’s own existence precedes an explanation of the world in terms of essences.

Choice for the epistemological variant

The pretensions of traditional epistemological ontology of a known world order can indeed be quite repulsive, and ontological security in the epistemological sense can assume arrogant and oppressive forms. It is not for nothing that thinking in categories of beings is often aptly referred to as ‘pigeonhole thinking’, or ‘pigeonholing’. Nevertheless, in the remainder of this article I will choose to use the word combination ontological security in an epistemological sense, and therefore not to use ontological security in an existentialist sense, as it recently has been widely used in psychiatry, sociology and international relations.

The two reasons for this are related. In the first place, there is the historical dominance of the epistemological interpretation of ontological security over the existentialist interpretation. Although the word combination ontological security has been coined by the existentialists, ‘security’ and the pursuit of it are also excellently linked to ontology in an epistemological sense. If moreover that epistemological ontology lasts for already thousands of years – compared to several decades for existentialist ontology – and if for  many generations in the West it was something to hold on to in some way, then it makes sense to take this interpretation of ontological security as a starting point.

This is all the more true as we saw that the first-sight similarity we observed between the dynamics of Levinas and those of the gender movement was also termed in terms of the ‘blurring of traditional concepts’. The word traditional therein refers to age-old traditions. So by definition it is about the ontological certainties with claims to knowledge, because the existentialist concepts are not old enough.

3. Reformulation of the thesis in terms of ontological security

At the beginning of the previous Section I indicated that the observed phenomena of the blurring of traditional concepts, the search for new words and the irritation about them can be discussed in terms of ontological (in)security. I find it desirable indeed to do so, because ontology plays a large role in the millennia-old Western philosophical tradition that continues to this day. The use of the term ontology makes it easier to refer to that tradition, and it will be seen that both Levinas’s position and the dynamics of the gender movement gain in comprehensability when the context of traditional ontology is included.

For the sake of clarity, it appeared necessary in the previous Section to demarcate the ontological security that I have in mind from existentialist ontological security. Now that it is clear that I am concerned with the epistemological variant of ontological security, I would like to reformulate my original thesis as follows:

The gender discussion on the one hand and Levinas’s thinking about sociality in Ramona Rat’s interpretation on the other are similar in the effects on ontological security they produce.

This reformulation allows me to use the terms ontological security and ontological insecurity to support the thesis. The substantiation will consist of an in-depth exploration of the three phenomena mentioned – concept blur, new language and consequent irritation – first for the gender movement (Section 4), then for Rat’s presentation of Levinas (Section 5). For both dynamics, I investigate what striving underlies the concept blur and the new language use and what the motive is for that striving. In the evaluation that follows (Section 6) I conclude that the gender movement and Levinas indeed strive parallel to each other to let go of ontological security, and that in doing so they are both motivated by a perspective of liberation. The question is to what extent the results of that aspiration are the same.

4. Problematization of categories in the gender movement

Blurring of traditional concepts

Insofar as there is a blurring of concepts in the gender debate, the reference to the ontological tradition is constantly imposed. This blurring is often expressed in the gender literature in the rejection of what we have already called ‘pigeonhole thinking’. In concrete terms, this usually concerns the division of humanity into strictly biologically and culturally demarcated categories of men and women. But characterized as a way of thinking, pigeonholing refers directly to classical ontology, i.e. to a much broader practice of categorization than just the distinction between male and female. After all, it tries to classify all beings – from heavenly bodies to grains of sand, from God to angels, and from people to insects – into categories of being on the basis of their properties, often ordered in a hierarchical way, ranging from higher to lower forms of being.

The word ‘pigeonholing’ may sound disrespectful, and in view of its focus on category demarcation, ontology is sometimes referred to, more neutrally, as ‘category theory’. But,  actually, ‘pigeonhole thinking’ excellently indicates what is happening. In any case, I notice that when explanations are given about what is going on in the gender movement, the word ‘pigeonholes’ is used abundantly. Journalist Sander Becker explains, for example, that non-binary people are people “who don’t feel at home in the binary pigeonholes of male or female” , and Menno Sedee that “intersex means that someone’s body (visible or invisible) does not fit into the male or female pigeonhole” . And for those who think that journalists in particular like to use the word ‘pigeonholes’, there is the statement by philosopher Frank Meester on the occasion of his latest book Why we cannot get the world fixed: “That’s how we are, yes. We all think in pigeonholes, but we never get everything packed in them” . That pigeonholing regularly targets the handed down ontological categories is apparent when in a text the word ‘pigeonhole’ is alternated with a description and is spoken, for example, of a growing group of people who no longer feel at home with “narrowly defined gender identities” .

Now you can deal with that in two ways, which I would call less and more reflexive. The less reflexive gender activists can live well with pigeonholes. They often do not oppose pigeonholing itself, but they oppose the definition of the contents of the holes or want to switch holes. The more reflexive gender activists question the existence of pigeonholes, they turn against pigeonholing itself. This group realizes that classical ontology has a long history of claiming to represent a necessary natural or divine order. So there is more at stake for this group than for the first group.

Some gender activists that have no objection to the two (or, including gay women and men: four) existing pigeonholes just want to be able to switch holes smoothly. For them it’s about making a clear choice for one of the two (or four) holes. Publicist Stephan Sanders amusingly describes how that worked when he came out as a homosexual. At the time, no one was fussing about his newly discovered orientation, Sanders was even encouraged to embrace it. In that sense he was free, but at the same time he felt trapped, “now in the homosexual role, which you also are supposed to consistently adhere to” according to the bystanders. It felt like a rendition “to the librarians of sex, who categorize our thoughts and label our behavior” . The old thinking in terms of categories is very much alive here.

Others likewise are not against pigeonholes, but find it problematic that the traditional thinking only leaves room for two holes when it comes to biological sex: that of man and woman, while there is a need for more intermediate shades. These people actually want more holes for defining gender identity. The Dutch Transgender Act is a thorn in the side for those who fight against the stringent dichotomy of only two alternatives. Because the Transgender Act states that for gender reassignment persons must be convinced that they belong to “the opposite sex”. But, according to the non-binary Senn van Beek , that is not always easy, because 3 to 6 percent of all Dutch people do not identify themselves (entirely) as a man or a woman, so two holes do not suffice for them. The proposed amendments to that law will provide that in the future everyone can determine their own gender, but for the time being there are only two flavors: male or female.

A number of female writers who like women think the indication ‘lesbian’ sounds too limited to themselves , because that word is linked to one of the two poles of man and woman, but they don’t object against other categories, for example with the labels gay, queer or gender diverse. Hadas Itzkovitch interviews four 25-year-old LGBTQ+ people , one of whom speaks of “shades of LGBTIQ+ identity” and another says “I really like men and women, and everything in between for that matter”, and it sounds like that in-between may be put in holes. In these statements, pigeonholes continue to play a role in determining identity.

It is more drastic when not only the pigeonholes, but the pigeonholing itself become the object of reflection and criticism. That happens with the more reflexive gender activists. Among them is anthropologist Rahil Roodsaz, who, together with colleague Katrien De Graeve, compiled the book Intimate revolutions: contrary in sex, love and care, in which scientists, writers and artists investigate the revolutionary potential of sex, love and care relationships. They discuss the problematic nature of categorization, for example when they talk about the standard of normality that is established by pigeonholing. Because of those standards, such as the traditional interpretation of the terms ‘man and woman’, “there is little room left to investigate whether you yourself have feelings and desires that deviate from this narrative. Which are surprising or alienating, because you did not expect them from yourself. At the same time, such a narrative can make you think you can fully understand the other person in advance: you are a woman, so you want this. You’re a man, so you’ll like that. Or: you are my child, so I can fully know your needs. Because of this, your partner, friendly relationship or child does not get a chance to be a little different or strange” . Here it becomes clear that not only the pigeonholes, but also thinking in terms of pigeonholes can be problematic. This causes the capture of essences and the bricking up of identities so that people can feel locked up. From this perspective, a way out of the pigeonholes requires a completely different way of thinking. While categorizing thinking feels so familiar and natural – because it connects to the age-old ontological tradition – you have to ask yourself whether this obviousness is justified.

This question, therefore, is asked by the more reflexive. They search the foundations of our thinking for potentially problematic presuppositions that predispose us to pigeonholing. Roodsaz and De Graeve touch on this when they say that we often assume “that some relationships are more natural, ‘more original’ or ‘real’ than others” . And Miriam Rasch dedicates her book Friction. Ethics in the age of dataism to the existence of erroneous presuppositions on a much broader level than just gender, but she makes it clear that taking traditional views for granted also touches the field of gender: “binarity is not a given at all, but a convention” . In other words: you can also get rid of it. The more reflexive gender activists therefore question the idea that the categories of ontology (the pigeonholes of pigeonholing) are an indisputable fact that together form an indisputable order. In doing so, they also question the substances that are often presented as initiators, foundations or guarantors of that order: God or nature. The pigeonholes are man-made. As a consequence, for these reflexives also the idea disappears that is traditionally connected with creation by God or nature, namely that creation forms a closed whole, a totality that can be known and understood.

The step that usually follows with many reflexives from this relativization of traditional ontology is the intention or the call to formulate another model of thought that should break through the closedness of the traditional model. For example, Rogier van der Wal does this in his discussion of Friction when he says: “Not everything is quantifiable, there is a surplus that escapes categorization, which John Cheney-Lippold in We are data calls ‘the else’ (…) . The unspeakable sets a limit for datafication: not everything can be translated into data and not everything has to be completely understandable” . In which statement we can safely relate data, in their quality of fixed pieces of knowledge, to the pigeonholes of the categories in which they are defined. “In the end”, says Miriam Rasch, “people and their stories are more important than data” . She thus claims a degree of freedom for humans with regard to determination by data.

An implication of this turn in thinking that wants to leave closedness behind is that there is no longer a whole on which thinking can get a grip. When totality breaks, things start to slip away from us. The pretense of complete understanding of people and things, characteristic of millennia of philosophy, is then abandoned. In this context, Roodsaz quotes the Portuguese poet Fernando Pessoa, who says that love can never go hand in hand with a full understanding of yourself or the other.  I am inclined to include Ian Morris in this reflexive group of gender activists. We saw earlier that she could not cope with the traditional strict dichotomy of man and woman: “It has never been so black and white for me: I have absorbed one into the other, I am now a bit of both” .

New language

Objection to existing pigeonholes characterizes all gender activists, but we just saw that for some blurring the boundaries of the pigeonholes is about creating new ones, while others (the more reflexive ones) question the categorization itself. We encounter the same distinction when it comes to the call for a new language. The former group of activists mainly search for new words, that is: for new pigeonholes; for the second, the entire designation system is at stake.

An example of the first approach is the trans woman who says: “Trans woman sounds too medical to me, so I came up with a new definition: Tranja! I like labels quite a bit; it helps me define who I am”. The group of writers we already encountered, who prefer not to use the word ‘lesbian’ anymore, but who do use the words gay, queer or gender diverse, also opt for this approach.

Examples of more radical language innovation are given in the first Section. Think of the gender-neutral ‘hen’ or attempts such as ‘mevreer’ and ‘menouw’. Typical of these new words is that there may still be categories, but that they are stretched in such a way that they acquire a more open character, where there is room for an theoretically infinite number of variants. The critical linguist Van Oostendorp declares that the issue is more than just a number of new words when he states that the emergence of gender-neutral pronouns cannot be seen as an organic development, but as something exceptional. “We all decide together: the language is now moving in this direction because we think it is necessary. That conscious intervention in how language develops is rare, especially when it comes to personal pronouns. They rarely change because they are ingrained in the foundation of a language.”  Sjoerd de Jong, philosopher and ombudsman of the national paper NRC, sees his newspaper struggling with gender and with what has come to be called ‘gender criticism’. He notes that there are philosophical questions underlying this that he would like to address, in order to clear up confusion about the concept of gender.  In other words, here a complete world view may be at stake.

Irritation and resistance

Two trends are reflected in the irritation caused by the gender discussion: for some it is limited to irritation about new words, others are also irritated by the fact that the gender discussion is jeopardizing an entire world view.
Using new words can feel forced. Linguist Marc van Oostendorp refers to this irritation on the occasion of a radio conversation about presenter Raven van Dorst, who identifies as non-binary: “All the interlocutors tried their best to use the correct pronouns, but it felt forced”. That in those cases it is only about words and not about the categories themselves can be seen from the NRC commentary on gender-neutral film awards: “Can you become more gender neutral without flattening the relievo between people by using neologisms such as ‘people who menstruate’ instead of ‘women’? Vigilance remains necessary against denying average differences between men and women, or imposing gender-neutral language and newspeak from above” .
The deep resistance that resents the fact that a complete order of being (ontology) is threatened is perhaps best expressed in the objection of ‘intrinsic disorder’ that some Christian churches use. This expression is not of recent date, and has been used by the churches against the phenomenon of homosexuality for much longer. But the word clearly indicates that in the perception of some groups a whole of ordering principles is shifting. One is confronted with ontological insecurity. The Polish organization Ordo Iuris strongly opposes the interest that is also growing in Poland for the LGBTI+ movement, and is the driving force behind the anti-LGBTI+ resolutions of the Polish parliament. Ordo Iuris spokesman Nikodem Bernaciak makes it clear what is at stake for him. In an interview , he calls the aspiration of the gender movement “ideologically motivated”, referring to a revolutionary worldview that threatens the whole of natural law, attachment to patriotic values and to values of the Christian heritage of the nation” – in short, the traditional ontology. When asked whether Ordo’s set of values is not also ideologically motivated, he responds almost indignantly: no, that is not the case, precisely because that order is nature- and God-given.

5.    Problematization of categories in Levinas

In the first Section, we have seen some examples of effects of Levinas’s treatment of sociality in the presentation of Rat, expressed in terms of blurring of traditional concepts, new words, and irritation about the blurring and new words. I will go into more detail about these effects below. It will turn out that for Levinas, as in the gender discussion, ontological security is at stake.

Blurring of traditional concepts

With Levinas we don’t have to beat around the bush. For the interpretation of the examples of his blurring use of language, it is not necessary in his case to make a distinction between a less and more reflexive interpretation, i.e. between less or more opposition to pigeonholing. Levinas is absolutely clear that, as far as he is concerned, a complete ontological system is under discussion. He fights ontological security. That can be seen from his substantiation, in Rat’s presentation, of the blurs we discussed in Section 1, which I’ll go over piece by piece. To clarify this substantiation, I first add another example of blurring in Levinas, namely the elimination of the difference between order and anarchy.

Order and anarchy

Levinas, says Rat, wants his reasoning to arrive at “a movement that is outside of order” , outside of any order. And outside of order, that is very precisely expressed in the term ‘anarchy’. “Anarchy (…) encompasses Levinas’s efforts to disrupt chronological and ontological order” . ‘Archè’ (Greek for ‘beginning’, NvdV) “is understood here as originarity and as principle itself, and hence becomes the building block of any kind of order” .

The prefix ‘an-‘ to anarchy could be understood as the opposite of archè. Archè and an-archè (anarchy) would then be each other’s opposites, and thus refer to each other and have a reference with a shared, more abstract, concept in common. Just as order and disorder have in common with each other that, as opposites, they both refer to the idea of order. In order the idea is realized, in disorder it is not, but both words have a relationship with that idea and thus share something. But Levinas does not want to understand archè and an-archè in that way. He wants to avoid calling archè and an-archè each other’s opposites, precisely because they would then have a relationship in common. An-archy is therefore not concerned with the opposite of archè (understood as ‘beginning’, thus creating time). Rat explains: “The privative tone of the ‘without’ (the ‘an’ from ‘an-archy’) does not have an annulling function that would transform the anarchical into the eternal, nor does it suggest some kind of primordiality (in the sense of the first order); instead it breaks down the very ‘logic’ of ordinarity and originarity itself” . And: “The form of anarchy that escapes both order and disorder is anarchy understood as without origin; (…) an-archy disturbs not only order (as disorder, or the contestation of order would do), but the very thinking in terms of order” .

The way in which Levinas does not simply want to oppose archè to an-archè because that again creates an order that he precisely does not want, is exemplary, according to Rat, for how Levinas deals with other familiar dichotomies: he systematically refuses all kinds of dualities, he rejects thinking in alternatives. “[H]ence we find here, once again, the refusal of dichotomies, a gesture repeated by Levinas throughout his work” . The various other paradoxes and forms of stretching of concepts that we encountered in Section 1 can now be placed in the frame that Levinas’s treatment of anarchy provides: he breaks the order-thinking by refusing dualities.

Active/passive

For that reason, Levinas blurs the familiar opposition between activity and passivity as we saw above. After all, that’s what happens when Levinas uses the phrase ‘prior to all passivity’, for example in Otherwise than being . Rat says: “By “prior” Levinas is not suggesting some kind of chronological hierarchy or order of causality. (…) he is not opposing passivity to activity; on the contrary, he continues to refuse dualities” . And: “[T]he point is precisely that pure passivity is beyond alternatives. By going beyond the dualities of passive-active, a move similar to the one observed in the case of an-archy and order, Levinas refuses what he considers to be a synthetical, unifying way of thinking”. It denotes a breach of the thinking of passivity and activity as counterparts. And the ‘synthetical, unifying way of thinking’ refers to classical ontology, which Levinas therefore rejects.

Inside/outside: on subjectivity

The same blurring applies to the dividing line between inside and outside, which Levinas stretches insofar as the subjectivity of the subject is concerned. While it is common to associate subjectivity with the inside of a subject, which is distinguished from the outside—including other subjects—by the boundary they have in common, Levinas according to Rat says, as we have already seen, that the distinction between inside and outside is disturbed. “The inside is not determined by the boundaries of the outside, but the self is from the start invaded by the outside” , where the ‘outside’ stands for the other. Self and other to a certain extent blend into each other, in Levinas’s new conception of subjectivity, according to Rat. As a result, the subject finds itself out of its closed inner sphere, it is, as it were, pushed out of its center in a movement of “de-position characteristic of the subject as sub-jectum, where the subject is out of its place, and in this sense, outside itself as ground. The interplay between inside and outside that the de-posed self creates is best articulated in Levinas’s notion of substitution” , on which later we get more.

Rat explains how analogous this is to Levinas’s treatment of (an)archy: “Due to its disruptive character, the hither side (inside, which is no longer an inside, NvdV) cannot be integrated into an order (e.g. the order of transcendence, the order of immanence, the order of dialectics, etc.). It represents, Levinas says, ‘a movement’ that is ‘outside of order.’ Outside of order, the hither side is anarchy: ‘On the hither side is expressed precisely in the term anarchy.’ Anarchy designates the way Levinas formulates the disruption, or the how of the hither side that we are looking for” .

Relationship without relationship

This also makes the expression ‘relationship without relationship’ somewhat clearer: Levinas’s expression is about an encounter without a common boundary or interface. Again he wants to avoid strict determination here, which a boundary invariably gives rise to. Thinking in terms of an encounter of opposites would be like thinking in terms of the resolution of opposites. Such thinking, says Rat, “would indeed lead to an abstract problem, as it would introduce relatedness and co-definition. This, in turn, would be a mere conceptual play of abstract notions, co-defining each other. In our view, Levinas has something different in mind” . Levinas consciously embraces the paradox.

Thematising without thematising

While in her book Rat is discussing the paradoxes presented above around her theme of ‘sociality in Levinas’, a fifth paradox arises. After all, if Levinas detaches himself in all sorts of ways from the pursuit of ontological security and the universal and abstract terms that go with it, this tendency also affects his treatment of the notion of sociality itself. It is inevitable that “Levinas’s philosophical stand (…) gives sociality the role of interrupting determination, while not forming a separate realm or a determined essence that causes the interruption” .

But, Rat then thinks, is that possible? Speaking of a notion and then mean something non-determining? Doesn’t formulating a notion come from the arsenal of ontological security, just like formulating a concept, discussing a theme, drafting a theory? Surely all of this is by definition determinative in nature and “part of a formal system of thought, and as such, it presupposes a certain degree of abstraction, which in its turn implies a unifying ideal principle?”  Formulating a notion would run counter to the pre-eminently anarchic character of sociality.

Here Rat comes across what is perhaps the most fundamental paradox inherent in Levinas’s thinking. Before she can continue with the treatment of sociality in Levinas, Rat must first switch back to the treatment of this determination paradox. The question that this paradox poses is “how we can speak in terms of notion, which usually means at least some degree of determination, when we, along with Levinas, need to sustain a resistance to the determination of the relation to the other. In other words, how can one disclose the resistance to disclosure, without damaging it? Why and how can we thematize the very impossibility of thematization?”  For Rat, this paradox gets to the heart of the matter: “Now we have reached the core of the problem: the difficulty of thematizing the very impossibility of thematization”. For Levinas himself, according to Rat, this question of how to deal with that paradox was also of essential importance, and so was his answer to that question. Levinas “points out that thematizing the refusal of thematization becomes a problem only if one continues to think in the logic of thematization, by applying the rules of unifying coherence applicable to a thematizing language. What Levinas is trying to underline is precisely the necessity of interrupting thematization and its rules of coherence, in order to resist its totalizing logic” .

From that answer and the instructions it contains, Rat can switch back to her treatment of the notion of sociality: “Our reading of sociality implies precisely the breakdown of any unifying principle that a universalized abstract concept would presuppose”. “[T]he notion of sociality designates a relation to the other(s) where the resistance to the determination of the other(s) remains important”. This can be achieved by seeing sociality as something that precedes determination and appropriation, because it has always been there.

New language

When it comes to the search for new language, Levinas, with few exceptions, does not create new words. He generally uses familiar words, but he gives them a new meaning. This applies, for example, to the words ‘substitution’, ‘saying’ and some personal pronouns. Inspired by Levinas, Rat gives a new meaning to the familiar word combination ‘inside out’.

Substitution

In discussing the blurring of the boundary between outside and inside in Levinas’s  conception of subjectivity, we came across the word ‘substitution’. We saw that that word has a place in Levinas’s attempts to relativize the mutual determination of inside and outside. The word denotes a shift of the self, “where the for itself is replaced by the for the other”. This displacement creates a different interpretation of the word ‘subjectivity’. In the essentialist view of the ontological tradition, the self is at the heart of its subjectivity; the substitution puts the self outside that core. Rat calls it the “the deposition of the self”.

Saying

The familiar word ‘saying’ takes on a special meaning in Levinas when he places it next to the word ‘said’ (that which has been said). In his efforts to move beyond determination and pigeonholing, Levinas redefines the relationship between Saying (le dire) and the Said (le dit). The Said stands for that which has already been recorded, because it has been spoken. Determination has already taken place. The Saying, on the other hand, which Levinas has in mind, precedes any recording. It is not so much “saying something, but the simple ‘here I am’ or ‘here’s me’ (me voici) of the emerging self. ‘Saying saying itself, without thematizing it, but exposing it again.’(…) In this way, the exposure of the Saying, its communication, is very different from thematization. It does not show anything (in the way the Said shows this as that), but it is contact without contracting, without transmission, holding nothing in common, but an opening in a response”. Saying ís communication, but much more it is the precondition for all communication.

In this context, Levinas himself still creates the new word ‘un-saying’ (French: dédire). Rat: “The Unsaying has the role of disrupting the way of thinking in alternatives, by constantly rescuing the Saying from being a mere correlate of the Said, through an interruption, a protest”.

Personal pronouns

Important familiar words to which Levinas gives new meaning according to Rat are the personal pronouns. This is interesting because they are also given a lot of emphasis in the treatment of gender.

The blurring of the subject by substitution, and Levinas’s distinction between the ‘self for oneself’ and the ‘self for the other’ acquire a counterpart in grammar. Levinas connects those positions with two grammatical cases: the for itself with the nominative, the subject form; and the other with the accusative, the direct object form. Thus subjectivity in substitution is no longer thought in terms of the words ego or I, but instead in terms of the word me. Rat says: “Taken in purely grammatical terms, the nominative form would characterize the subject case, while the accusative would be the object case, and would relate back to the nominative (subject). However, Levinas proposes the subject as accusative: ‘And it is the sense of the ‘oneself,’ that accusative that derives from no nominative; it is the very fact of finding oneself while losing oneself’”.

Inside out

The observation that with Levinas the distinction between the inner world and the outer world is becoming looser, and his interpretation of the word substitution as the interchange of self and other inspires Rat to introduce the word ‘inside out’ as an indication of what Levinas is referring to. She explains this as follows: “Although Levinas never discusses it in terms of inside-out dimension of the relation to the other, he certainly calls attention, as we have seen, to the self on the “hither side [en deçà] of my identity.” For the purpose of this thesis, it is important to bring forth this inside-out dimension of the relation to the other, so that later on, sociality cannot be confused with a notion of social relations focusing on the relation itself, or with a pure subjectivism representing a relative point of view” .

Just to be sure, she adds that by using the term inside out, she does not mean to restore the dichotomy of inside and outside. It is precisely about the “the very disruption of the two poles “inside” and “outside,” “in” and “out,” without one becoming another”.

Irritation

Levinas’s blurring of concepts can cause all sorts of annoyances. I limit myself to Rat’s comments. In addition, I briefly discuss the ontological insecurity that his attack on ontological security can evoke.

Rat speaks out in some places about the lack of clarity in Levinas. For example, she is sometimes forced, “due to a certain lack of clarity and some inconsistencies in Levinas’s thought” , to make choices of interpretation, and thereby distance herself from some parts of his work. In general, she then opts for the more radical and ontology-critical interpretation. For example, she opposes the traditional conception of sociality in dyadic terms , which runs counter to many of Levinas’s anti-dualistic views, but which can be found in his work.

For thinkers other than Rat, ontology-critical thinking sometimes goes too far, or runs the risk to go too far. They show a perhaps healthy revulsion or skepticism towards ontology-critical thinkers in general. So it’s not just about Levinas, but also about, for example, Foucault, Derrida, Baudrillard or Latour. In her book A Cyborg Manifesto, Donna Haraway points out the danger that attacks on ontological security can trigger trauma and feelings of insecurity. As mentioned, she is not referring specifically to Levinas’s work, but given its tendency we have observed, his work may contain that risk. Haraway warns that in criticizing stable and totalizing categories, “we risk lapsing into boundless difference and giving up on the confusing task of making partial, real connection” . There is a danger that critical thinking à la Levinas will degenerate into “a celebration of the reign of the undetermined – of ontological insecurity as such – which would be a reign of chaos. It is a (plea for the) search for new life strategies which would not exclude death from life but which would emphasize a life within ambivalence”.

6.    Evaluation

Evaluating, you can say that Levinas in Rat’s presentation and some segments in the gender movement have a number of things in common. They share the aspiration of letting go of ontological security, and they share the motivation for that aspiration. The question is to what extent the results of that striving are the same.

Striving for letting go of ontological security

Quite a bit is happening, both in Levinas and in the gender movement; an attempt is made to let go of ontological security, that much has become clear in Sections 4 and 5. Looking at the thesis, I therefore think that we can confirm it. Certainly if we adjust it slightly by inserting the word ‘want’: Levinas according to Rat and the gender discussion are similar in the effects on ontological security that they want to bring about. Because of the oppression (for the gender movement) or the totalization (for Levinas) that emanates from traditional ontology, they want to breach pigeonholed thinking. Levinas and the gender movement definitely have this aspiration in common.

Which is not to say that it always works. But, you could say, they also have those failures in common. In the gender movement, the rejection of existing pigeonholes appears in many cases to lead to new ones. And in his struggle against ontological security, Levinas also understands that it is not possible to completely dispense with determinative order thinking and theory. Rat rightly remarks that “a full escape from the theoretical is impossible, and Levinas knows this well”.

Motivation for that striving

What the gender movement and Rat’s portrayal of Levinas also share is the motivation for that endeavour. They agree that the determination and constraint that ontological security entails costs us too much.

The gender movement points to the constraint of traditional narrow definitions of identity and subjectivity, stemming from a desire for ontological security. The gender activists’s critique focuses on efforts to achieve ontological security, described by Rossdale as efforts “to securitize subjectivity, which means an intensified search for one stable identity (regardless of its actual existence)”. Rossdale believes that sharply demarcating subjectivity and identity comes at a cost: this is done “along axes of self and other in ways which achieve ontological security at the expense of those others”. That is, through exclusion and violence. After all, he quotes Catarina Kinnvall, “[t]he construction of self and other is (…) almost always a way to define superior and inferior beings. Increasing ontological security for one person or group is thus likely to decrease security for those not included in the nationalist and/or religious discourse”. And Frank Dekkers, information officer at Transvisie Go, states that if children are not free to experience their identity, this generally leads to more problems than solutions.

The Levinasian keyword for designating the cost of ontological security is totalization. In many places Levinas speaks of totalizing ontology that dominates our thinking and life. As we saw, the division of the world into categories or opposites that refer to each other has totalizing features for Levinas, precisely because those categories and opposites form a closed world with each other. It is for this reason, Rat says, that in Totality and Infinity, “the break with thinking in dichotomies is expressed in the form of a break with totality, since an all-embracing, totalizing gaze is what makes the dichotomies function as they refer back to one another”.

And how does this evil effect of totalization take place? Because totalization names everything in terms of a mediating larger whole and thus blocks communication between people – described by Levinas as the direct and unmediated “exposure of one to the other”. For real communication – or real speaking – “the escape from a totalizing system of thematization”  is necessary. As we saw, Rat also regularly speaks of ‘disruption’ . You could call it a liberating conception of sociality.

Result of that endeavor

What the fight against ontological security aims at, both in the gender movement and in Levinas, according to Rat, is: liberation from ‘forms of closure’, in Rossdale’s terms . To what extent is that aspiration being fulfilled in the gender movement and in Levinas?

The gender dynamics offers real examples of liberation. In response to the introduction of gender-neutral film prizes, the Dutch newspaper NRC writes in its commentary that it is striking again and again how logical gender developments in society actually are “at a time when a growing group of people no longer feel at home with narrowly defined gender identities” . We’ve already read about Ian Morris and the relief she felt. Another transgender woman, Denny Agassi, says of herself that she is not taken seriously everywhere after coming out, but that does not alter the fact that “I know myself to be real”. In an article about the increasing gender fluidity, Jonathan Walford of the Fashion History Museum in Cambridge says that he no longer adheres to the distinction between men’s and women’s clothes when it comes to fashion: “It was a serious life hack to discover that we can make our own rules”.

With regard to the work of Levinas, I do not know of such grateful testimonies of liberation from forms of closure. That is why I sometimes wonder: is it perhaps too intellectual what he is doing, can such language as he uses still cover reality? But there is something to that. After all, if the gender movement – which can indeed boast of concrete examples of liberation – thinks about what it is doing and what else is needed, it appears to end up with exactly what Levinas is doing.

For example, Rossdale mentions as the aim of his article to get a feeling for possibilities to flee from the terrain of ontological security/insecurity. Because “aspirations toward (or claims of) ontological security enact significant limitations (…) insofar as they close down the question of the subject precisely at the point where it might more productively be kept open” . Reading Levinas according to Rat’s interpretation is useful here. And Judith Butler “restates the problems of ontological security in a manner which celebrates precisely that which Laing rejects, acknowledging the subject’s instability, non-autonomy and biographical incompleteness as a potent source for ethical reflection” . “The pre-established or prior contours of the subject are a limited and limiting space from which to begin ethical reflection” . Rossdale mentions that Butler was partly inspired by Levinas in this.

I therefore conclude that, in their shared pursuit of resistance to forms of closure in favor of a new conception of subjectivity, Queer Theory and interpretations of Levinas will, as yet, be able to continue to fertilize each other.


Literature

Butler, J. (2001) Giving an Account of Oneself. In: Diacritics, 31(4), 22-40.

Gustafsson, K. and Krickel-Choi, N. (2020) Returning to the roots of ontological security: insights from the existentialist anxiety literature. In: European Journal of International Relations 26(3), pp. 875-895. Londen: Sage.

Haraway, Donna (1991) “A Cyborg Manifesto: Science, Technology and Socialist-Feminism in the Late Twentieth Century”, in Haraway, ed. Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. London: Free Association Books.

Kinnvall, C. (2004) Globalization and Religious Nationalism: Self, Identity, and the Search for Ontological Security. In: Political Psychology, 25(5): 741-767.

Laing, R. (2010) The Divided Self. [1960] London: Penguin.

Levinas, E. (1991) Totality and Infinity. An Essay on Exteriority. Originally: [1961] Totalité et Infini, translated by Alphonso Lingis. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Levinas, E. (1998) Otherwise than Being, or Beyond essence. Originally: [1974] Autrement qu´être ou au-dela-de l´essence, translated by Alphonso Lingis. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

Meester, F. (2021) Waarom we de wereld niet rond kunnen krijgen. Utrecht: Ten Have.

Rasch, M. (2021) Frictie. Ethiek in tijden van dataïsme. Amsterdam: De Bezige Bij.

Rat, R. (2016) Un-common Sociality. Thinking sociality with Levinas. Huddinge: Södertörn Philosophical Studies.

Roodsaz, R. and De Graeve, K. (2021) Intieme revoluties: tegendraads in seks, liefde en zorg. Amsterdam: Boom.

Rossdale, Ch. (2015) Enclosing Critique: The Limits of Ontological Security. In: International Political Sociology, Vol. 9, pp. 369-389.