Home
Home
Nederlands
Texts/
Articles
Workshops
Naud van der Ven
Contact
|
Review of Ontological
Fundamentals for Ethical Management. Heidegger
and the Corporate World
by Dominik
Heil
2011,
Dordrecht: Springer
With Ontological
Fundamentals for Ethical Management. Heidegger and the
Corporate World Dominik Heil wrote a
cross-border book, and this in several respects. Not
only does he cross discipline boundaries: by relating
the philosopher Heidegger to trends in organizational
science and by translating in a plausible way
Heidegger’s thinking to Management and Organization. In
addition, in his analysis of the problems in this border
area, he digs deeper than many other books dare to do.
To enjoy the book, you have
to be able to bear Heidegger’s jargon. But those who are
not allergic to it – as for me, it may have at times
something fascinating about it – get an interesting
argumentation about the question whether or not the
shortcomings of Western management thinking can be
sensibly discussed starting from Heidegger's ideas. In
that argumentation those shortcomings are clearly
outlined, Heidegger’s thought is clearly presented and
it is made plausible that this thought may in many
respects be an answer to the shortcomings.
Objective and motivation
The objective of the book
is to clear the road for a new organizational ethics.
But, Heil says, ethics does not hang in a void. It can
only be based on thorough understanding of what that
ethics belongs to, in this case the corporate world.
Therefore, even though the book is about ethics, the
author will mainly deal with the question of what an
organization actually is: what is “the very nature of
the corporation”(12)?
Thus the book’s ambition is to provide, via that road, a
basis for business ethics. It wants to pass beyond a
metaphorical way of speaking about the organization, and
to get at “a literal, accurate and authentic account of
the corporation and its organisation” (13). And Heil
wants to achieve that by operating, with Heidegger, in
an ontological way, because “[b]eing clear about the
ontological nature of an entity is critical when dealing
with it appropriately, regardless of the kind of entity
one is dealing with” (21). Whereby ontology must be
understood as being that part of philosophy that is
concerned with determining the “very nature or Being”
(15) of entities, and thus in the case of this book of
the entity that is called the corporation.
Because of its emphasis on what is essential (“the very
nature or Being”) Heil calls this approach to
corporations more fundamental than other approaches such
as by Coase, Drucker, and Lawrence & Lorsch, because
they don’t arrive at an ontological account. And Gareth
Morgan got caught by metaphors: “Metaphorical statements
can highlight certain aspects of an entity but, since
they are not literal, they do not capture the true
nature of the entity. They also can not completely
describe the entity as what it is in its very nature”
(18).
The fundamental approach which Heil has in mind consists
is “to look at what determines the contemporary
discourse on the theory and practice of ethics, which is
already taken for granted at the most fundamental level”
(7). He wants to expose those taken for granted
startingpoints, because only then the subsequent
phenomena can be explained and perhaps changed.
As mentioned, ultimately Heil’s concern is with ethics,
and it is from that area that stems his motivation for
writing the book. Because Heil observes that a cynical
view prevails in the field of organizational studies,
which states that corporations are not ethical (4). And
that, by way of compensation for that shortcoming, codes
and rules and value statements are being established
(3), which have little to do with ethics and chiefly
lead to calculating compliance behavior. Heil cannot
agree with that state of affairs and this discontent
leads him to wonder whether a corporation can or cannot
show concern for people.
In addition, he notes that according to many studies,
scientific organization studies performs poorly, because
the scientific principles are meagre. The dominant
conception of the corporation as a machine, stemming
from Descartes, is simply impractical, “insufficient to
recognize the doable and possible in an actual
situation” (26) and the failure rate of organizational
expert projects is high (27). According to Heil that
could be improved, via a richer understanding of
corporations, by broadening horizons.
It is Heil’s intention to perform this broadening of
horizons through Heidegger. He emphasizes that defining
in a broader way what a corporation is, and therewith
what the field of organizational studies is, should be
considered as a philosophical exercise, and not a
science. “The decisions of what belongs in an academic
discipline and what is to be considered useful or
useless in this discipline is not something that can be
decided within the field. It is decided when the field
is constituted. The constitution of a field is a
philosophical undertaking” (20). So Heil is not going to
commit science. That means that he is not going to prove
anything but will only try to make certain views more
plausible. The reader is invited to get convinced.
The choice to perform his investigation on the basis of
Heidegger’s work may cause surprise, Heil realizes.
After all, Heidegger had nothing to do with
corporations, nor with the usual conception of ethics as
a set of universal moral principles, values or a single
general maxim. But “Heidegger was able to ask questions
at a more primordial level and it is this that makes him
promising as a guide for the attempt to lead a
philosophical inquiry about corporations and their
management” (34).
The impoverishment of corporate ethics compared to
original ethics which disturbs Heil so much, can be
traced back with the help of Heidegger – beyond
Descartes – to Aristotle. So, for the digging up of the
original, broader oriented ethics Heil ends up with the
pre-Aristotelian thinkers, because these depart from “a
more primordial thinking which in the case of ethics
refers to an understanding of ethos, the word that
‘ethics’ is derived from” (10). The difference is that
“in contemporary ethics we look predominantly at
character, and in this sense really the characteristics
of a human being, while an inquiry into ethos really
means an inquiry into our human way of dwelling, that
which we already find ourselves in” (11). Heidegger also
refers to this as “an ongoing inquiry into the truth of
Being”.
Heidegger thematizes this difference between original
and atrophied ethics, both with regard to Aristotle’s
thinking and to its impact in Descartes and later
philosophers. He shows us the totalitarian nature of our
system: it constantly renders all phenomena in the same
set of terms and reduces our world to an
oppressive totality “that reveals everything in such a
way that humans are compelled to develop and employ all
of these technical instruments and gadgets” ( 94) and
that people themselves appear as human resources. Heil
chooses Heidegger for his guide because of the
possibilities which the latter offers to make this kind
of analyses.
The argument
Crucial for the line of Heil’s argument is his focus on
Heidegger’s fundamental ontology, ie the latter’s view
on the basic categories into which entities can be
classified in this world. Heidegger distinguishes
four of them, namely physical objects, non-human
organisms, humans and works. This classification is
established on the basis of Heidegger’s fundamental
ontological criterion, which focuses on an entity’s
relationship to Being.
The four types of relationships to Being which Heidegger
distinguishes are defined by using the concept of
‘world’. “World means the always already familiar
horizon upon which everyday human existence moves with
absolute confidence and within which humans make sense
of both their environment and themselves. World is the
significant whole or referential totality within which
things, plants, animals and humans, including ourselves,
make sense to us and fit into our lives” (53). World is
thus a concept that belongs to humans, because primarily
it makes theír lives intelligible. Therefore the
definition of the category of humans – using the word
‘world’ – is as follows: human beings acquire a world.
But by extension ‘world’ can also be used for the other
categories of entities. Thus Heidegger characterizes
physical objects as ‘worldless’, because they have no
access to an understanding of their environment or
themselves. Non-human organisms he calls ‘world-poor’
because their access is only limited. And a work he
describes as ‘setting up a world’, because a work (eg a
work of art) brings to life the kind of meaningful
background by which comprehensibility becomes possible
at all.
Heil then discusses the question to which category the
corporation belongs. To that end, he walks along the
various options and he ends up at the category of works.
The corporation is a work because the corporation
creates a whole full of meanings that can be understood
by humans. “Works, by setting up a world, also open up
an a priori understanding of the Being of entities and
of Being as such. From a fundamental ontological
perspective, works do participate in Being and,
therefore, by definition have an ethical import if
ethics is understood orginally as pondering the abode of
humans, which is first and foremost Being itself” (80).
Hereby the agenda for the rest of the book has been
established: “[I]t is critical that the investigation
focuses on the corporation’s relation to Being or the
truth of Being” (47).
The hallmark of a work is that it conjures up a world,
and the dominant form of organization as we know it does
so indeed. But, says Heil, in the case of a corporation
that is a flawed world. Because there, in the wake of
Descartes, objects and technology are central: “[World]
is replaced by the very nature of technology, which
Heidegger names ‘em-bankment’ [Ge-stell]. Em-bankment is
of the same kind as world but it is not the same at all”
(97). The main difference is that embankment is less
meaningful, because although it produces meanings, their
significance is always scant: “[E]verything shows up as
an asset: physical objects, plants and animals, humans”
(97). Everything becomes instrumental, reduced to the
value it has for economic or technical control.
And the problem is: it is almost impossible to talk
about it. The thinking in instrumental terms allows no
critical meta-discussion, because whatever is said is
encapsulated in the instrumental thinking. Thus, “[t]o
inform people about them being an asset is entirely
senseless, because, on the one hand, this view is
obvious and correct within em-bankment and, on the other
hand, it does not give humans any hint about their very
nature” (125).
The job is therefore to achieve a richer conception of
the ‘work’ of the organization, a view which does more
justice to the meaning-creating character of a ‘work’.
That does not necessarily lead to a break with
technology, but rather to a search for access to the
true nature of technology. Connection therewith allows
qualified use of technology without impoverishing the
world and it does more justice to the nature of things,
nature and people.
Heidegger calls this simultaneous ‘yes’ and ‘no’ to
technology ‘the-letting-things-be’, which can be also
understood as “granting something its own very nature or
way of being” (132). This is achieved by contemplative
thinking, in distinction to calculative thinking. By
contemplation “we can create or re-create the company in
such a way that it sets up a world rather than
em-bankment” (135). A richer language is required for
that.
Contemplative thinking is, according to Heil,
pre-ethical and that determination takes him back to his
real topic: ethics. Because contemplation may not be
moral thinking, but it provides the basis for this
(140). The connection is via the finding that, when
people are merely seen as factors of production, the
awareness is lost that they can create their own future
and are ‘world-acquiring’ (69).
The Body Shop demonstrates how the desired connection
can be established. Because the values formulated by the
Body Shop may possibly be considered as “an articulation
of an ethos, a way and depth of knowing the very nature
of the entities that are involved in the business in
various forms and ways” (166). The Body Shop shows to
have an eye for the specific nature of the different
entity categories: for example, for the vulnerability of
animals, and for people as ‘openness-for-Being’, who
have intercourse among themselves in the form of a
dialogue, ie through sharing of worlds.
When the ‘work’ which is the corporation is understood
in this original sense, there is, according to Heil, no
longer question of ‘corporation’ but of ‘enterprise’.
And the work that people have to do for it are its
creation and its maintenance. That is subtle, in fact
artistic work which will never yield security. Instead
of more of the same there is always created something
new. In a way Heil summons managers to become artists
(116).
Comments
As may appear from the above overview, Heil wrote a
thorough study. The argumentation is clear, Heidegger’s
thought is well displayed and there is a plausible
translation of Heidegger to organizations. These are
great achievements.
Somewhat inexplicable therefore in this knowledgeable
book is the wrong spelling of res cogitans. This Cartesian
expression is consistently presented as “res cognitans”.
Could this perhaps be a matter of wrong autocorrection?
Then yet it is surprising that that eluded the notice of
the editors and proofreaders.
In addition there are a few comments to be made
concerning content. The first of these is that the book
relies heavily on the assumption of a crystal clear
distinction between ‘very nature’ and something which
then must be ‘not-very-nature’, or in other words
between authentic and non-authentic. True enough there
are a few critical questions in this respect, for
example when it comes to the essence of the corporation:
“The question that then arises is how it can be
established that the interpretation of the very nature
of the corporation and its management is not just
another opinion in the market place of countless other
opinions, but is a genuine contribution instead?” (41).
That is an important question indeed, but it is not
really answered. However, that does not prevent the
author from very often speaking in the sequel about the
‘very nature of entities’ or from assuming that it can
be known. Eventually Heil believes to be able to get at
a “unified understanding emerging in the literature of
what a corporation actually is from an ontological
perspective” (28).
A certain caution seems to exist in this respect when he
says that “any truth is at the same time un-truth”
(148). A consequence of that statement, I would say, is
that this un-truth also relativizes the knowledge of the
‘very nature’ of things, and would make the word ‘very’
less suitable. But that suggestion is pushed aside
at other places, for example, in a sentence as the
following: “This willing that is given by the knowing of
a world and the very nature of entities in a world is
what Heidegger calls resolvedness [Ent-schlossenheit]”
(154), from which you may infer that the very nature of
entities is known. And that, at least at one time, there
is but one very nature of an entity (whether it be a
corporation or something else). Apparently plurality of
deepest insights does exist in Heidegger (and Heil) over
time, but not at one and the same moment.
A second comment as regards content stems from the
first. If it would be possible at all to determine in an
unequivocal way the deepest character of an entity, who
will be the one to determine its content? Who is
going to perform the important task of contemplating the
very nature of an entity, in short: the task of
ontology. As we have seen, Heidegger attributes this
task to philosophy: “The constitution of a field is a
philosophical undertaking” (ie the determination of the
very nature of the entities is a philosophical task).
And even though the method of fundamental ontology is
descriptive and not proving, its results are claimed to
be universally valid.
That is quite a claim and Heil knows the objections that
may exist against it. He cites Powell who rejects the
ontological approach, “stating that any ontological
understanding will inevitably lead to dogmatism,
illusion, despair and escalating chains of ideology”
(31). In his treatment of this objection Heil points out
that Heidegger emphatically wanted not to impose dogmas.
In addition, Heil states that expliciting the underlying
assumptions makes possible a critical dialogue.
“What both empiricists and pragmatists tend to overlook,
however, is the way that empiricism and every pragmatic
solution implicitly make transcendental claims that can
and do lead to the escalating chains of ideology,
dogmatism and, consequently, illusion and despair that
Powell seeks to avoid” (31).
Heil is right about that, of course. But what guarantees
does he have for the impartiality of philosophers in the
determination of the very nature of an entity? As for
me, the combination of on the one hand the assumption of
the existence of a clear and knowable very nature, and
on the other hand the allocation of the authority to do
universally valid statements thereabout to a
Heideggerian contemplative philosopher, keeps raising
questions.
My third comment comes from one of Heil’s findings that
to a large extent I can agree with. Namely from his
observation of the impoverishment and alienation that
prevails in management and organization. I also think it
is sympathetic that Heil looks for an answer to that in
broadening perspectives. For instance when he, in line
with Heidegger, conceives of man as much fuller than the
dominant organizational climate does, namely not as an
asset or resource but as world-acquiring. And as someone
who can, through dialogue, be addressed about the worlds
that he shares with others in Mitdasein.
But what is disturbing, in Heil and in Heidegger, is the
illusion that Mitdasein as it were trouble-free matches
with the world-acquiring character of the individual. As
far as it does match, one can indeed say that
“being-with others in the sense of sharing a world
allows for and constitutes the possibility of empathy
and genuine concern for other humans as humans. As such
it is the basis for the authentic concern for the other
and others that is fundamental to and constitutes the
possibility for any genuine ethics” (164).
But the matching to my belief is only half of the story.
In many cases the world-acquiring attitude will for
individuals also lead to tensions and fractures with the
others with whom he shares a world. And not always with
the prospect of reconciling the differences, because
people cán really be different. Then more is required
than an ethics based on a shared world. Then dealing
with differences is at least as essential.
Literature
Heil, D. (2011) Ontological Fundamentals for Ethical
Management. Heidegger and the Corporate World.
Dordrecht: Springer.
|